英語聽力 學英語,練聽力,上聽力課堂! 注冊 登錄
> 在線聽力 > 有聲讀物 > 世界名著 > 譯林版·物種起源 >  第11篇

雙語《物種起源》 第十章 論生物的地質演替

所屬教程:譯林版·物種起源

瀏覽:

2022年07月01日

手機版
掃描二維碼方便學習和分享

CHAPTER X ON THE GEOLOGICAL SUCCESSION OF ORGANIC BEINGS

On the slow and successive appearance of new species—On their different rates of change—Species once lost do not reappear—Groups of species follow the same general rules in their appearance and disappearance as do single species—On Extinction—On simultaneous changes in the forms of life throughout the world—On the affinities of extinct species to each other and to living species—On the state of development of ancient forms—On the succession of the same types within the same areas—Summary of preceding and present chapters.

Let us now see whether the several facts and rules relating to the geological succession of organic beings, better accord with the common view of the immutability of species, or with that of their slow and gradual modification, through descent and natural selection.

New species have appeared very slowly, one after another, both on the land and in the waters. Lyell has shown that it is hardly possible to resist the evidence on this head in the case of the several tertiary stages; and every year tends to fill up the blanks between them, and to make the percentage system of lost and new forms more gradual. In some of the most recent beds, though undoubtedly of high antiquity if measured by years, only one or two species are lost forms, and only one or two are new forms, having here appeared for the first time, either locally, or, as far as we know, on the face of the earth. If we may trust the observations of Philippi in Sicily, the successive changes in the marine inhabitants of that island have been many and most gradual. The secondary formations are more broken; but, as Bronn has remarked, neither the appearance nor disappearance of their many now extinct species has been simultaneous in each separate formation.

Species of different genera and classes have not changed at the same rate, or in the same degree. In the oldest tertiary beds a few living shells may still be found in the midst of a multitude of extinct forms. Falconer has given a striking instance of a similar fact, in an existing crocodile associated with many strange and lost mammals and reptiles in the sub-Himalayan deposits. The Silurian Lingula differs but little from the living species of this genus; whereas most of the other Silurian Molluscs and all the Crustaceans have changed greatly. The productions of the land seem to change at a quicker rate than those of the sea, of which a striking instance has lately been observed in Switzerland. There is some reason to believe that organisms, considered high in the scale of nature, change more quickly than those that are low: though there are exceptions to this rule. The amount of organic change, as Pictet has remarked, does not strictly correspond with the succession of our geological formations; so that between each two consecutive formations, the forms of life have seldom changed in exactly the same degree. Yet if we compare any but the most closely related formations, all the species will be found to have undergone some change. When a species has once disappeared from the face of the earth, we have reason to believe that the same identical form never reappears. The strongest apparent exception to this latter rule, is that of the so-called “colonies” of M. Barrande, which intrude for a period in the midst of an older formation, and then allow the pre-existing fauna to reappear; but Lyell's explanation, namely, that it is a case of temporary migration from a distinct geographical province, seems to me satisfactory.

These several facts accord well with my theory. I believe in no fixed law of development, causing all the inhabitants of a country to change abruptly, or simultaneously, or to an equal degree. The process of modification must be extremely slow. The variability of each species is quite independent of that of all others. Whether such variability be taken advantage of by natural selection, and whether the variations be accumulated to a greater or lesser amount, thus causing a greater or lesser amount of modification in the varying species, depends on many complex contingencies,—on the variability being of a beneficial nature, on the power of intercrossing, on the rate of breeding, on the slowly changing physical conditions of the country, and more especially on the nature of the other inhabitants with which the varying species comes into competition. Hence it is by no means surprising that one species should retain the same identical form much longer than others; or, if changing, that it should change less. We see the same fact in geographical distribution; for instance, in the land-shells and coleopterous insects of Madeira having come to differ considerably from their nearest allies on the continent of Europe, whereas the marine shells and birds have remained unaltered. We can perhaps understand the apparently quicker rate of change in terrestrial and in more highly organised productions compared with marine and lower productions, by the more complex relations of the higher beings to their organic and inorganic conditions of life, as explained in a former chapter. When many of the inhabitants of a country have become modified and improved, we can understand, on the principle of competition, and on that of the many all-important relations of organism to organism, that any form which does not become in some degree modified and improved, will be liable to be exterminated. Hence we can see why all the species in the same region do at last, if we look to wide enough intervals of time, become modified; for those which do not change will become extinct.

In members of the same class the average amount of change, during long and equal periods of time, may, perhaps, be nearly the same; but as the accumulation of long-enduring fossiliferous formations depends on great masses of sediment having been deposited on areas whilst subsiding, our formations have been almost necessarily accumulated at wide and irregularly intermittent intervals; consequently the amount of organic change exhibited by the fossils embedded in consecutive formations is not equal. Each formation, on this view, does not mark a new and complete act of creation, but only an occasional scene, taken almost at hazard, in a slowly changing drama.

We can clearly understand why a species when once lost should never reappear, even if the very same conditions of life, organic and inorganic, should recur. For though the offspring of one species might be adapted (and no doubt this has occurred in innumerable instances) to fill the exact place of another species in the economy of nature, and thus supplant it; yet the two forms—the old and the new—would not be identically the same; for both would almost certainly inherit different characters from their distinct progenitors. For instance, it is just possible, if our fantail-pigeons were all destroyed, that fanciers, by striving during long ages for the same object, might make a new breed hardly distinguishable from our present fantail; but if the parent rock-pigeon were also destroyed, and in nature we have every reason to believe that the parent-form will generally be supplanted and exterminated by its improved offspring, it is quite incredible that a fantail, identical with the existing breed, could be raised from any other species of pigeon, or even from the other well-established races of the domestic pigeon, for the newly-formed fantail would be almost sure to inherit from its new progenitor some slight characteristic differences.

Groups of species, that is, genera and families, follow the same general rules in their appearance and disappearance as do single species, changing more or less quickly, and in a greater or lesser degree. A group does not reappear after it has once disappeared; or its existence, as long as it lasts, is continuous. I am aware that there are some apparent exceptions to this rule, but the exceptions are surprisingly few, so few, that E. Forbes, Pictet, and Woodward (though all strongly opposed to such views as I maintain) admit its truth; and the rule strictly accords with my theory. For as all the species of the same group have descended from some one species, it is clear that as long as any species of the group have appeared in the long succession of ages, so long must its members have continuously existed, in order to have generated either new and modified or the same old and unmodified forms. Species of the genus Lingula, for instance, must have continuously existed by an unbroken succession of generations, from the lowest Silurian stratum to the present day.

We have seen in the last chapter that the species of a group sometimes falsely appear to have come in abruptly; and I have attempted to give an explanation of this fact, which if true would have been fatal to my views. But such cases are certainly exceptional; the general rule being a gradual increase in number, till the group reaches its maximum, and then, sooner or later, it gradually decreases. If the number of the species of a genus, or the number of the genera of a family, be represented by a vertical line of varying thickness, crossing the successive geological formations in which the species are found, the line will sometimes falsely appear to begin at its lower end, not in a sharp point, but abruptly; it then gradually thickens upwards, sometimes keeping for a space of equal thickness, and ultimately thins out in the upper beds, marking the decrease and final extinction of the species. This gradual increase in number of the species of a group is strictly conformable with my theory; as the species of the same genus, and the genera of the same family, can increase only slowly and progressively; for the process of modification and the production of a number of allied forms must be slow and gradual,—one species giving rise first to two or three varieties, these being slowly converted into species, which in their turn produce by equally slow steps other species, and so on, like the branching of a great tree from a single stem, till the group becomes large.

On Extinction.—We have as yet spoken only incidentally of the disappearance of species and of groups of species. On the theory of natural selection the extinction of old forms and the production of new and improved forms are intimately connected together. The old notion of all the inhabitants of the earth having been swept away at successive periods by catastrophes, is very generally given up, even by those geologists, as Elie de Beaumont, Murchison, Barrande, etc., whose general views would naturally lead them to this conclusion. On the contrary, we have every reason to believe, from the study of the tertiary formations, that species and groups of species gradually disappear, one after another, first from one spot, then from another, and finally from the world. Both single species and whole groups of species last for very unequal periods; some groups, as we have seen, having endured from the earliest known dawn of life to the present day; some having disappeared before the close of the palaeozoic period. No fixed law seems to determine the length of time during which any single species or any single genus endures. There is reason to believe that the complete extinction of the species of a group is generally a slower process than their production: if the appearance and disappearance of a group of species be represented, as before, by a vertical line of varying thickness, the line is found to taper more gradually at its upper end, which marks the progress of extermination, than at its lower end, which marks the first appearance and increase in numbers of the species. In some cases, however, the extermination of whole groups of beings, as of ammonites towards the close of the secondary period, has been wonderfully sudden.

The whole subject of the extinction of species has been involved in the most gratuitous mystery. Some authors have even supposed that as the individual has a definite length of life, so have species a definite duration. No one I think can have marvelled more at the extinction of species, than I have done. When I found in La Plata the tooth of a horse embedded with the remains of Mastodon, Megatherium, Toxodon, and other extinct monsters, which all co-existed with still living shells at a very late geological period, I was filled with astonishment; for seeing that the horse, since its introduction by the Spaniards into South America, has run wild over the whole country and has increased in numbers at an unparalleled rate, I asked myself what could so recently have exterminated the former horse under conditions of life apparently so favourable. But how utterly groundless was my astonishment! Professor Owen soon perceived that the tooth, though so like that of the existing horse, belonged to an extinct species. Had this horse been still living, but in some degree rare, no naturalist would have felt the least surprise at its rarity; for rarity is the attribute of a vast number of species of all classes, in all countries. If we ask ourselves why this or that species is rare, we answer that something is unfavourable in its conditions of life; but what that something is, we can hardly ever tell. On the supposition of the fossil horse still existing as a rare species, we might have felt certain from the analogy of all other mammals, even of the slow-breeding elephant, and from the history of the naturalisation of the domestic horse in South America, that under more favourable conditions it would in a very few years have stocked the whole continent. But we could not have told what the unfavourable conditions were which checked its increase, whether some one or several contingencies, and at what period of the horse's life, and in what degree, they severally acted. If the conditions had gone on, however slowly, becoming less and less favourable, we assuredly should not have perceived the fact, yet the fossil horse would certainly have become rarer and rarer, and finally extinct;—its place being seized on by some more successful competitor.

It is most difficult always to remember that the increase of every living being is constantly being checked by unperceived injurious agencies; and that these same unperceived agencies are amply sufficient to cause rarity, and finally extinction. We see in many cases in the more recent tertiary formations, that rarity precedes extinction; and we know that this has been the progress of events with those animals which have been exterminated, either locally or wholly, through man's agency. I may repeat what I published in 1845, namely, that to admit that species generally become rare before they become extinct—to feel no surprise at the rarity of a species, and yet to marvel greatly when it ceases to exist, is much the same as to admit that sickness in the individual is the forerunner of death—to feel no surprise at sickness, but when the sick man dies, to wonder and to suspect that he died by some unknown deed of violence.

The theory of natural selection is grounded on the belief that each new variety, and ultimately each new species, is produced and maintained by having some advantage over those with which it comes into competition; and the consequent extinction of less-favoured forms almost inevitably follows. It is the same with our domestic productions: when a new and slightly improved variety has been raised, it at first supplants the less improved varieties in the same neighbourhood; when much improved it is transported far and near, like our short-horn cattle, and takes the place of other breeds in other countries. Thus the appearance of new forms and the disappearance of old forms, both natural and artificial, are bound together. In certain flourishing groups, the number of new specific forms which have been produced within a given time is probably greater than that of the old forms which have been exterminated; but we know that the number of species has not gone on indefinitely increasing, at least during the later geological periods, so that looking to later times we may believe that the production of new forms has caused the extinction of about the same number of old forms.

The competition will generally be most severe, as formerly explained and illustrated by examples, between the forms which are most like each other in all respects. Hence the improved and modified descendants of a species will generally cause the extermination of the parent-species; and if many new forms have been developed from any one species, the nearest allies of that species, i.e. the species of the same genus, will be the most liable to extermination. Thus, as I believe, a number of new species descended from one species, that is a new genus, comes to supplant an old genus, belonging to the same family. But it must often have happened that a new species belonging to some one group will have seized on the place occupied by a species belonging to a distinct group, and thus caused its extermination; and if many allied forms be developed from the successful intruder, many will have to yield their places; and it will generally be allied forms, which will suffer from some inherited inferiority in common. But whether it be species belonging to the same or to a distinct class, which yield their places to other species which have been modified and improved, a few of the sufferers may often long be preserved, from being fitted to some peculiar line of life, or from inhabiting some distant and isolated station, where they have escaped severe competition. For instance, a single species of Trigonia, a great genus of shells in the secondary formations, survives in the Australian seas; and a few members of the great and almost extinct group of Ganoid fishes still inhabit our fresh waters. Therefore the utter extinction of a group is generally, as we have seen, a slower process than its production.

With respect to the apparently sudden extermination of whole families or orders, as of Trilobites at the close of the palaeozoic period and of Ammonites at the close of the secondary period, we must remember what has been already said on the probable wide intervals of time between our consecutive formations; and in these intervals there may have been much slow extermination. Moreover, when by sudden immigration or by unusually rapid development, many species of a new group have taken possession of a new area, they will have exterminated in a correspondingly rapid manner many of the old inhabitants; and the forms which thus yield their places will commonly be allied, for they will partake of some inferiority in common.

Thus, as it seems to me, the manner in which single species and whole groups of species become extinct, accords well with the theory of natural selection. We need not marvel at extinction; if we must marvel, let it be at our presumption in imagining for a moment that we understand the many complex contingencies, on which the existence of each species depends. If we forget for an instant, that each species tends to increase inordinately, and that some check is always in action, yet seldom perceived by us, the whole economy of nature will be utterly obscured. Whenever we can precisely say why this species is more abundant in individuals than that; why this species and not another can be naturalised in a given country; then, and not till then, we may justly feel surprise why we cannot account for the extinction of this particular species or group of species.

On the Forms of Life changing almost simultaneously throughout the World.—Scarcely any palaeontological discovery is more striking than the fact, that the forms of life change almost simultaneously throughout the world. Thus our European Chalk formation can be recognised in many distant parts of the world, under the most different climates, where not a fragment of the mineral chalk itself can be found; namely, in North America, in equatorial South America, in Tierra del Fuego, at the Cape of Good Hope, and in the peninsula of India. For at these distant points, the organic remains in certain beds present an unmistakeable degree of resemblance to those of the Chalk. It is not that the same species are met with; for in some cases not one species is identically the same, but they belong to the same families, genera, and sections of genera, and sometimes are similarly characterised in such trifling points as mere superficial sculpture. Moreover other forms, which are not found in the Chalk of Europe, but which occur in the formations either above or below, are similarly absent at these distant points of the world. In the several successive palaeozoic formations of Russia, Western Europe and North America, a similar parallelism in the forms of life has been observed by several authors: so it is, according to Lyell, with the several European and North American tertiary deposits. Even if the few fossil species which are common to the Old and New Worlds be kept wholly out of view, the general parallelism in the successive forms of life, in the stages of the widely separated palaeozoic and tertiary periods, would still be manifest, and the several formations could be easily correlated.

These observations, however, relate to the marine inhabitants of distant parts of the world: we have not sufficient data to judge whether the productions of the land and of fresh water change at distant points in the same parallel manner. We may doubt whether they have thus changed: if the Megatherium, Mylodon, Macrauchenia, and Toxodon had been brought to Europe from La Plata, without any information in regard to their geological position, no one would have suspected that they had coexisted with still living sea-shells; but as these anomalous monsters coexisted with the Mastodon and Horse, it might at least have been inferred that they had lived during one of the latter tertiary stages.

When the marine forms of life are spoken of as having changed simultaneously throughout the world, it must not be supposed that this expression relates to the same thousandth or hundred-thousandth year, or even that it has a very strict geological sense; for if all the marine animals which live at the present day in Europe, and all those that lived in Europe during the pleistocene period (an enormously remote period as measured by years, including the whole glacial epoch), were to be compared with those now living in South America or in Australia, the most skilful naturalist would hardly be able to say whether the existing or the pleistocene inhabitants of Europe resembled most closely those of the southern hemisphere. So, again, several highly competent observers believe that the existing productions of the United States are more closely related to those which lived in Europe during certain later tertiary stages, than to those which now live here; and if this be so, it is evident that fossiliferous beds deposited at the present day on the shores of North America would hereafter be liable to be classed with somewhat older European beds. Nevertheless, looking to a remotely future epoch, there can, I think, be little doubt that all the more modern marine formations, namely, the upper pliocene, the pleistocene and strictly modern beds, of Europe, North and South America, and Australia, from containing fossil remains in some degree allied, and from not including those forms which are only found in the older underlying deposits, would be correctly ranked as simultaneous in a geological sense.

The fact of the forms of life changing simultaneously, in the above large sense, at distant parts of the world, has greatly struck those admirable observers, MM. de Verneuil and d'Archiac. After referring to the parallelism of the palaeozoic forms of life in various parts of Europe, they add, “If struck by this strange sequence, we turn our attention to North America, and there discover a series of analogous phenomena, it will appear certain that all these modifications of species, their extinction, and the introduction of new ones, cannot be owing to mere changes in marine currents or other causes more or less local and temporary, but depend on general laws which govern the whole animal kingdom.” M. Barrande has made forcible remarks to precisely the same effect. It is, indeed, quite futile to look to changes of currents, climate, or other physical conditions, as the cause of these great mutations in the forms of life throughout the world, under the most different climates. We must, as Barrande has remarked, look to some special law. We shall see this more clearly when we treat of the present distribution of organic beings, and find how slight is the relation between the physical conditions of various countries, and the nature of their inhabitants.

This great fact of the parallel succession of the forms of life throughout the world, is explicable on the theory of natural selection. New species are formed by new varieties arising, which have some advantage over older forms; and those forms, which are already dominant, or have some advantage over the other forms in their own country, would naturally oftenest give rise to new varieties or incipient species; for these latter must be victorious in a still higher degree in order to be preserved and to survive. We have distinct evidence on this head, in the plants which are dominant, that is, which are commonest in their own homes, and are most widely diffused, having produced the greatest number of new varieties. It is also natural that the dominant, varying, and far-spreading species, which already have invaded to a certain extent the territories of other species, should be those which would have the best chance of spreading still further, and of giving rise in new countries to new varieties and species. The process of diffusion may often be very slow, being dependent on climatal and geographical changes, or on strange accidents, but in the long run the dominant forms will generally succeed in spreading. The diffusion would, it is probable, be slower with the terrestrial inhabitants of distinct continents than with the marine inhabitants of the continuous sea. We might therefore expect to find, as we apparently do find, a less strict degree of parallel succession in the productions of the land than of the sea.

Dominant species spreading from any region might encounter still more dominant species, and then their triumphant course, or even their existence, would cease. We know not at all precisely what are all the conditions most favourable for the multiplication of new and dominant species; but we can, I think, clearly see that a number of individuals, from giving a better chance of the appearance of favourable variations, and that severe competition with many already existing forms, would be highly favourable, as would be the power of spreading into new territories. A certain amount of isolation, recurring at long intervals of time, would probably be also favourable, as before explained. One quarter of the world may have been most favourable for the production of new and dominant species on the land, and another for those in the waters of the sea. If two great regions had been for a long period favourably circumstanced in an equal degree, whenever their inhabitants met, the battle would be prolonged and severe; and some from one birthplace and some from the other might be victorious. But in the course of time, the forms dominant in the highest degree, wherever produced, would tend everywhere to prevail. As they prevailed, they would cause the extinction of other and inferior forms; and as these inferior forms would be allied in groups by inheritance, whole groups would tend slowly to disappear; though here and there a single member might long be enabled to survive.

Thus, as it seems to me, the parallel, and, taken in a large sense, simultaneous, succession of the same forms of life throughout the world, accords well with the principle of new species having been formed by dominant species spreading widely and varying; the new species thus produced being themselves dominant owing to inheritance, and to having already had some advantage over their parents or over other species; these again spreading, varying, and producing new species. The forms which are beaten and which yield their places to the new and victorious forms, will generally be allied in groups, from inheriting some inferiority in common; and therefore as new and improved groups spread throughout the world, old groups will disappear from the world; and the succession of forms in both ways will everywhere tend to correspond.

There is one other remark connected with this subject worth making. I have given my reasons for believing that all our greater fossiliferous formations were deposited during periods of subsidence; and that blank intervals of vast duration occurred during the periods when the bed of the sea was either stationary or rising, and likewise when sediment was not thrown down quickly enough to embed and preserve organic remains. During these long and blank intervals I suppose that the inhabitants of each region underwent a considerable amount of modification and extinction, and that there was much migration from other parts of the world. As we have reason to believe that large areas are affected by the same movement, it is probable that strictly contemporaneous formations have often been accumulated over very wide spaces in the same quarter of the world; but we are far from having any right to conclude that this has invariably been the case, and that large areas have invariably been affected by the same movements. When two formations have been deposited in two regions during nearly, but not exactly the same period, we should find in both, from the causes explained in the foregoing paragraphs, the same general succession in the forms of life; but the species would not exactly correspond; for there will have been a little more time in the one region than in the other for modification, extinction, and immigration.

I suspect that cases of this nature have occurred in Europe. Mr. Prestwich, in his admirable Memoirs on the eocene deposits of England and France, is able to draw a close general parallelism between the successive stages in the two countries; but when he compares certain stages in England with those in France, although he finds in both a curious accordance in the numbers of the species belonging to the same genera, yet the species themselves differ in a manner very difficult to account for, considering the proximity of the two areas,—unless, indeed, it be assumed that an isthmus separated two seas inhabited by distinct, but contemporaneous, faunas. Lyell has made similar observations on some of the later tertiary formations. Barrande, also, shows that there is a striking general parallelism in the successive Silurian deposits of Bohemia and Scandinavia; nevertheless he finds a surprising amount of difference in the species. If the several formations in these regions have not been deposited during the same exact periods,—a formation in one region often corresponding with a blank interval in the other,—and if in both regions the species have gone on slowly changing during the accumulation of the several formations and during the long intervals of time between them; in this case, the several formations in the two regions could be arranged in the same order, in accordance with the general succession of the form of life, and the order would falsely appear to be strictly parallel; nevertheless the species would not all be the same in the apparently corresponding stages in the two regions.

On the Affinities of extinct Species to each other, and to living forms.—Let us now look to the mutual affinities of extinct and living species. They all fall into one grand natural system; and this fact is at once explained on the principle of descent. The more ancient any form is, the more, as a general rule, it differs from living forms. But, as Buckland long ago remarked, all fossils can be classed either in still existing groups, or between them. That the extinct forms of life help to fill up the wide intervals between existing genera, families, and orders, cannot be disputed. For if we confine our attention either to the living or to the extinct alone, the series is far less perfect than if we combine both into one general system. With respect to the Vertebrata, whole pages could be filled with striking illustrations from our great palaeontologist, Owen, showing how extinct animals fall in between existing groups. Cuvier ranked the Ruminants and Pachyderms, as the two most distinct orders of mammals; but Owen has discovered so many fossil links, that he has had to alter the whole classification of these two orders; and has placed certain pachyderms in the same sub-order with ruminants: for example, he dissolves by fine gradations the apparently wide difference between the pig and the camel. In regard to the Invertebrata, Barrande, and a higher authority could not be named, asserts that he is every day taught that palaeozoic animals, though belonging to the same orders, families, or genera with those living at the present day, were not at this early epoch limited in such distinct groups as they now are.

Some writers have objected to any extinct species or group of species being considered as intermediate between living species or groups. If by this term it is meant that an extinct form is directly intermediate in all its characters between two living forms, the objection is probably valid. But I apprehend that in a perfectly natural classification many fossil species would have to stand between living species, and some extinct genera between living genera, even between genera belonging to distinct families. The most common case, especially with respect to very distinct groups, such as fish and reptiles, seems to be, that supposing them to be distinguished at the present day from each other by a dozen characters, the ancient members of the same two groups would be distinguished by a somewhat lesser number of characters, so that the two groups, though formerly quite distinct, at that period made some small approach to each other.

It is a common belief that the more ancient a form is, by so much the more it tends to connect by some of its characters groups now widely separated from each other. This remark no doubt must be restricted to those groups which have undergone much change in the course of geological ages; and it would be difficult to prove the truth of the proposition, for every now and then even a living animal, as the Lepidosiren, is discovered having affinities directed towards very distinct groups. Yet if we compare the older Reptiles and Batrachians, the older Fish, the older Cephalopods, and the eocene Mammals, with the more recent members of the same classes, we must admit that there is some truth in the remark.

Let us see how far these several facts and inferences accord with the theory of descent with modification. As the subject is somewhat complex, I must request the reader to turn to the diagram in the fourth chapter. We may suppose that the numbered letters represent genera, and the dotted lines diverging from them the species in each genus. The diagram is much too simple, too few genera and too few species being given, but this is unimportant for us. The horizontal lines may represent successive geological formations, and all the forms beneath the uppermost line may be considered 14 14 as extinct. The three existing genera, a14, q14, p14, will form a small family; b14 and f14 a closely allied family or sub-family; and o14, e14, m14, a third family. These three families, together with the many extinct genera on the several lines of descent diverging from the parent-form A, will form an order; for all will have inherited something in common from their ancient and common progenitor. On the principle of the continued tendency to divergence of character, which was formerly illustrated by this diagram, the more recent any form is, the more it will generally differ from its ancient progenitor. Hence we can understand the rule that the most ancient fossils differ most from existing forms. We must not, however, assume that divergence of character is a necessary contingency; it depends solely on the descendants from a species being thus enabled to seize on many and different places in the economy of nature. Therefore it is quite possible, as we have seen in the case of some Silurian forms, that a species might go on being slightly modified in relation to its slightly altered conditions of life, and yet retain throughout a vast period the same general characteristics. This is represented in the diagram by the letter F14.

All the many forms, extinct and recent, descended from A, make, as before remarked, one order; and this order, from the continued effects of extinction and divergence of character, has become divided into several sub-families and families, some of which are supposed to have perished at different periods, and some to have endured to the present day.

By looking at the diagram we can see that if many of the extinct forms, supposed to be embedded in the successive formations, were discovered at several points low down in the series, the three existing families on the uppermost line would be rendered less distinct from each other. If, for instance, the genera a1, a5, a5, f8, m3, m6, m9 were disinterred, these three families would be so closely linked together that they probably would have to be united into one great family, in nearly the same manner as has occurred with ruminants and pachyderms. Yet he who objected to call the extinct genera, which thus linked the living genera of three families together, intermediate in character, would be justified, as they are intermediate, not directly, but only by a long and circuitous course through many widely different forms. If many extinct forms were to be discovered above one of the middle horizontal lines or geological formations—for instance, above No. VI.—but none from beneath this line, then only the two families on the left hand (namely, a14, etc., and b14, etc.) would have to be united into one family; and the two other families (namely, a14 to f14 now including five genera, and o14 to m14) would yet remain distinct. These two families, however, would be less distinct from each other than they were before the discovery of the fossils. If, for instance, we suppose the existing genera of the two families to differ from each other by a dozen characters, in this case the genera, at the early period marked VI., would differ by a lesser number of characters; for at this early stage of descent they have not diverged in character from the common progenitor of the order, nearly so much as they subsequently diverged. Thus it comes that ancient and extinct genera are often in some slight degree intermediate in character between their modified descendants, or between their collateral relations.

In nature the case will be far more complicated than is represented in the diagram; for the groups will have been more numerous, they will have endured for extremely unequal lengths of time, and will have been modified in various degrees. As we possess only the last volume of the geological record, and that in a very broken condition, we have no right to expect, except in very rare cases, to fill up wide intervals in the natural system, and thus unite distinct families or orders. All that we have a right to expect, is that those groups, which have within known geological periods undergone much modification, should in the older formations make some slight approach to each other; so that the older members should differ less from each other in some of their characters than do the existing members of the same groups; and this by the concurrent evidence of our best palaeontologists seems frequently to be the case.

Thus, on the theory of descent with modification, the main facts with respect to the mutual affinities of the extinct forms of life to each other and to living forms, seem to me explained in a satisfactory manner. And they are wholly inexplicable on any other view.

On this same theory, it is evident that the fauna of any great period in the earth's history will be intermediate in general character between that which preceded and that which succeeded it. Thus, the species which lived at the sixth great stage of descent in the diagram are the modified offspring of those which lived at the fifth stage, and are the parents of those which became still more modified at the seventh stage; hence they could hardly fail to be nearly intermediate in character between the forms of life above and below. We must, however, allow for the entire extinction of some preceding forms, and for the coming in of quite new forms by immigration, and for a large amount of modification, during the long and blank intervals between the successive formations. Subject to these allowances, the fauna of each geological period undoubtedly is intermediate in character, between the preceding and succeeding faunas. I need give only one instance, namely, the manner in which the fossils of the Devonian system, when this system was first discovered, were at once recognised by palaeontologists as intermediate in character between those of the overlying carboniferous, and underlying Silurian system. But each fauna is not necessarily exactly intermediate, as unequal intervals of time have elapsed between consecutive formations.

It is no real objection to the truth of the statement, that the fauna of each period as a whole is nearly intermediate in character between the preceding and succeeding faunas, that certain genera offer exceptions to the rule. For instance, mastodons and elephants, when arranged by Dr. Falconer in two series, first according to their mutual affinities and then according to their periods of existence, do not accord in arrangement. The species extreme in character are not the oldest, or the most recent; nor are those which are intermediate in character, intermediate in age. But supposing for an instant, in this and other such cases, that the record of the first appearance and disappearance of the species was perfect, we have no reason to believe that forms successively produced necessarily endure for corresponding lengths of time: a very ancient form might occasionally last much longer than a form elsewhere subsequently produced, especially in the case of terrestrial productions inhabiting separated districts. To compare small things with great: if the principal living and extinct races of the domestic pigeon were arranged as well as they could be in serial affinity, this arrangement would not closely accord with the order in time of their production, and still less with the order of their disappearance; for the parent rock-pigeon now lives; and many varieties between the rock-pigeon and the carrier have become extinct; and carriers which are extreme in the important character of length of beak originated earlier than short-beaked tumblers, which are at the opposite end of the series in this same respect.

Closely connected with the statement, that the organic remains from an intermediate formation are in some degree intermediate in character, is the fact, insisted on by all palaeontologists, that fossils from two consecutive formations are far more closely related to each other, than are the fossils from two remote formations. Pictet gives as a well-known instance, the general resemblance of the organic remains from the several stages of the chalk formation, though the species are distinct in each stage. This fact alone, from its generality, seems to have shaken Professor Pictet in his firm belief in the immutability of species. He who is acquainted with the distribution of existing species over the globe, will not attempt to account for the close resemblance of the distinct species in closely consecutive formations, by the physical conditions of the ancient areas having remained nearly the same. Let it be remembered that the forms of life, at least those inhabiting the sea, have changed almost simultaneously throughout the world, and therefore under the most different climates and conditions. Consider the prodigious vicissitudes of climate during the pleistocene period, which includes the whole glacial period, and note how little the specific forms of the inhabitants of the sea have been affected.

On the theory of descent, the full meaning of the fact of fossil remains from closely consecutive formations, though ranked as distinct species, being closely related, is obvious. As the accumulation of each formation has often been interrupted, and as long blank intervals have intervened between successive formations, we ought not to expect to find, as I attempted to show in the last chapter, in any one or two formations all the intermediate varieties between the species which appeared at the commencement and close of these periods; but we ought to find after intervals, very long as measured by years, but only moderately long as measured geologically, closely allied forms, or, as they have been called by some authors, representative species; and these we assuredly do find. We find, in short, such evidence of the slow and scarcely sensible mutation of specific forms, as we have a just right to expect to find.

On the state of Development of Ancient Forms.—There has been much discussion whether recent forms are more highly developed than ancient. I will not here enter on this subject, for naturalists have not as yet defined to each other's satisfaction what is meant by high and low forms. But in one particular sense the more recent forms must, on my theory, be higher than the more ancient; for each new species is formed by having had some advantage in the struggle for life over other and preceding forms. If under a nearly similar climate, the eocene inhabitants of one quarter of the world were put into competition with the existing inhabitants of the same or some other quarter, the eocene fauna or flora would certainly be beaten and exterminated; as would a secondary fauna by an eocene, and a palaeozoic fauna by a secondary fauna. I do not doubt that this process of improvement has affected in a marked and sensible manner the organisation of the more recent and victorious forms of life, in comparison with the ancient and beaten forms; but I can see no way of testing this sort of progress. Crustaceans, for instance, not the highest in their own class, may have beaten the highest molluscs. From the extraordinary manner in which European productions have recently spread over New Zealand, and have seized on places which must have been previously occupied, we may believe, if all the animals and plants of Great Britain were set free in New Zealand, that in the course of time a multitude of British forms would become thoroughly naturalized there, and would exterminate many of the natives. On the other hand, from what we see now occurring in New Zealand, and from hardly a single inhabitant of the southern hemisphere having become wild in any part of Europe, we may doubt, if all the productions of New Zealand were set free in Great Britain, whether any considerable number would be enabled to seize on places now occupied by our native plants and animals. Under this point of view, the productions of Great Britain may be said to be higher than those of New Zealand. Yet the most skilful naturalist from an examination of the species of the two countries could not have foreseen this result.

Agassiz insists that ancient animals resemble to a certain extent the embryos of recent animals of the same classes; or that the geological succession of extinct forms is in some degree parallel to the embryological development of recent forms. I must follow Pictet and Huxley in thinking that the truth of this doctrine is very far from proved. Yet I fully expect to see it hereafter confirmed, at least in regard to subordinate groups, which have branched off from each other within comparatively recent times. For this doctrine of Agassiz accords well with the theory of natural selection. In a future chapter I shall attempt to show that the adult differs from its embryo, owing to variations supervening at a not early age, and being inherited at a corresponding age. This process, whilst it leaves the embryo almost unaltered, continually adds, in the course of successive generations, more and more difference to the adult.

Thus the embryo comes to be left as a sort of picture, preserved by nature, of the ancient and less modified condition of each animal. This view may be true, and yet it may never be capable of full proof. Seeing, for instance, that the oldest known mammals, reptiles, and fish strictly belong to their own proper classes, though some of these old forms are in a slight degree less distinct from each other than are the typical members of the same groups at the present day, it would be vain to look for animals having the common embryological character of the Vertebrata, until beds far beneath the lowest Silurian strata are discovered—a discovery of which the chance is very small.

On the Succession of the same Types within the same areas, during the later tertiary periods.—Mr. Clift many years ago showed that the fossil mammals from the Australian caves were closely allied to the living marsupials of that continent. In South America, a similar relationship is manifest, even to an uneducated eye, in the gigantic pieces of armour like those of the armadillo, found in several parts of La Plata; and Professor Owen has shown in the most striking manner that most of the fossil mammals, buried there in such numbers, are related to South American types. This relationship is even more clearly seen in the wonderful collection of fossil bones made by MM. Lund and Clausen in the caves of Brazil. I was so much impressed with these facts that I strongly insisted, in 1839 and 1845, on this “l(fā)aw of the succession of types,”—on “this wonderful relationship in the same continent between the dead and the living.” Professor Owen has subsequently extended the same generalisation to the mammals of the Old World. We see the same law in this author's restorations of the extinct and gigantic birds of New Zealand. We see it also in the birds of the caves of Brazil. Mr. Woodward has shown that the same law holds good with sea-shells, but from the wide distribution of most genera of molluscs, it is not well displayed by them. Other cases could be added, as the relation between the extinct and living land-shells of Madeira; and between the extinct and living brackish-water shells of the Aralo-Caspian Sea.

Now what does this remarkable law of the succession of the same types within the same areas mean? He would be a bold man, who after comparing the present climate of Australia and of parts of South America under the same latitude, would attempt to account, on the one hand, by dissimilar physical conditions for the dissimilarity of the inhabitants of these two continents, and, on the other hand, by similarity of conditions, for the uniformity of the same types in each during the later tertiary periods. Nor can it be pretended that it is an immutable law that marsupials should have been chiefly or solely produced in Australia; or that Edentata and other American types should have been solely produced in South America. For we know that Europe in ancient times was peopled by numerous marsupials; and I have shown in the publications above alluded to, that in America the law of distribution of terrestrial mammals was formerly different from what it now is. North America formerly partook strongly of the present character of the southern half of the continent; and the southern half was formerly more closely allied, than it is at present, to the northern half. In a similar manner we know from Falconer and Cautley's discoveries, that northern India was formerly more closely related in its mammals to Africa than it is at the present time. Analogous facts could be given in relation to the distribution of marine animals.

On the theory of descent with modification, the great law of the long enduring, but not immutable, succession of the same types within the same areas, is at once explained; for the inhabitants of each quarter of the world will obviously tend to leave in that quarter, during the next succeeding period of time, closely allied though in some degree modified descendants. If the inhabitants of one continent formerly differed greatly from those of another continent, so will their modified descendants still differ in nearly the same manner and degree. But after very long intervals of time and after great geographical changes, permitting much inter-migration, the feebler will yield to the more dominant forms, and there will be nothing immutable in the laws of past and present distribution.

It may be asked in ridicule, whether I suppose that the megatherium and other allied huge monsters have left behind them in South America the sloth, armadillo, and anteater, as their degenerate descendants. This cannot for an instant be admitted. These huge animals have become wholly extinct, and have left no progeny. But in the caves of Brazil, there are many extinct species which are closely allied in size and in other characters to the species still living in South America; and some of these fossils may be the actual progenitors of living species. It must not be forgotten that, on my theory, all the species of the same genus have descended from some one species; so that if six genera, each having eight species, be found in one geological formation, and in the next succeeding formation there be six other allied or representative genera with the same number of species, then we may conclude that only one species of each of the six older genera has left modified descendants, constituting the six new genera. The other seven species of the old genera have all died out and have left no progeny. Or, which would probably be a far commoner case, two or three species of two or three alone of the six older genera will have been the parents of the six new genera; the other old species and the other whole genera having become utterly extinct. In failing orders, with the genera and species decreasing in numbers, as apparently is the case of the Edentata of South America, still fewer genera and species will have left modified blood-descendants.

Summary of the preceding and present Chapters.—I have attempted to show that the geological record is extremely imperfect; that only a small portion of the globe has been geologically explored with care; that only certain classes of organic beings have been largely preserved in a fossil state; that the number both of specimens and of species, preserved in our museums, is absolutely as nothing compared with the incalculable number of generations which must have passed away even during a single formation; that, owing to subsidence being necessary for the accumulation of fossiliferous deposits thick enough to resist future degradation, enormous intervals of time have elapsed between the successive formations; that there has probably been more extinction during the periods of subsidence, and more variation during the periods of elevation, and during the latter the record will have been least perfectly kept; that each single formation has not been continuously deposited; that the duration of each formation is, perhaps, short compared with the average duration of specific forms; that migration has played an important part in the first appearance of new forms in any one area and formation; that widely ranging species are those which have varied most, and have oftenest given rise to new species; and that varieties have at first often been local. All these causes taken conjointly, must have tended to make the geological record extremely imperfect, and will to a large extent explain why we do not find interminable varieties, connecting together all the extinct and existing forms of life by the finest graduated steps.

He who rejects these views on the nature of the geological record, will rightly reject my whole theory. For he may ask in vain where are the numberless transitional links which must formerly have connected the closely allied or representative species, found in the several stages of the same great formation. He may disbelieve in the enormous intervals of time which have elapsed between our consecutive formations; he may overlook how important a part migration must have played, when the formations of any one great region alone, as that of Europe, are considered; he may urge the apparent, but often falsely apparent, sudden coming in of whole groups of species. He may ask where are the remains of those infinitely numerous organisms which must have existed long before the first bed of the Silurian system was deposited: I can answer this latter question only hypothetically, by saying that as far as we can see, where our oceans now extend they have for an enormous period extended, and where our oscillating continents now stand they have stood ever since the Silurian epoch; but that long before that period, the world may have presented a wholly different aspect; and that the older continents, formed of formations older than any known to us, may now all be in a metamorphosed condition, or may lie buried under the ocean.

Passing from these difficulties, all the other great leading facts in palaeontology seem to me simply to follow on the theory of descent with modification through natural selection. We can thus understand how it is that new species come in slowly and successively; how species of different classes do not necessarily change together, or at the same rate, or in the same degree; yet in the long run that all undergo modification to some extent. The extinction of old forms is the almost inevitable consequence of the production of new forms. We can understand why when a species has once disappeared it never reappears. Groups of species increase in numbers slowly, and endure for unequal periods of time; for the process of modification is necessarily slow, and depends on many complex contingencies. The dominant species of the larger dominant groups tend to leave many modified descendants, and thus new sub-groups and groups are formed. As these are formed, the species of the less vigorous groups, from their inferiority inherited from a common progenitor, tend to become extinct together, and to leave no modified offspring on the face of the earth. But the utter extinction of a whole group of species may often be a very slow process, from the survival of a few descendants, lingering in protected and isolated situations. When a group has once wholly disappeared, it does not reappear; for the link of generation has been broken.

We can understand how the spreading of the dominant forms of life, which are those that oftenest vary, will in the long run tend to people the world with allied, but modified, descendants; and these will generally succeed in taking the places of those groups of species which are their inferiors in the struggle for existence. Hence, after long intervals of time, the productions of the world will appear to have changed simultaneously.

We can understand how it is that all the forms of life, ancient and recent, make together one grand system; for all are connected by generation. We can understand, from the continued tendency to divergence of character, why the more ancient a form is, the more it generally differs from those now living. Why ancient and extinct forms often tend to fill up gaps between existing forms, sometimes blending two groups previously classed as distinct into one; but more commonly only bringing them a little closer together. The more ancient a form is, the more often, apparently, it displays characters in some degree intermediate between groups now distinct; for the more ancient a form is, the more nearly it will be related to, and consequently resemble, the common progenitor of groups, since become widely divergent. Extinct forms are seldom directly intermediate between existing forms; but are intermediate only by a long and circuitous course through many extinct and very different forms. We can clearly see why the organic remains of closely consecutive formations are more closely allied to each other, than are those of remote formations; for the forms are more closely linked together by generation: we can clearly see why the remains of an intermediate formation are intermediate in character.

The inhabitants of each successive period in the world's history have beaten their predecessors in the race for life, and are, in so far, higher in the scale of nature; and this may account for that vague yet ill-defined sentiment, felt by many palaeontologists, that organisation on the whole has progressed. If it should hereafter be proved that ancient animals resemble to a certain extent the embryos of more recent animals of the same class, the fact will be intelligible. The succession of the same types of structure within the same areas during the later geological periods ceases to be mysterious, and is simply explained by inheritance.

If then the geological record be as imperfect as I believe it to be, and it may at least be asserted that the record cannot be proved to be much more perfect, the main objections to the theory of natural selection are greatly diminished or disappear. On the other hand, all the chief laws of palaeontology plainly proclaim, as it seems to me, that species have been produced by ordinary generation: old forms having been supplanted by new and improved forms of life, produced by the laws of variation still acting round us, and preserved by Natural Selection.

第十章 論生物的地質演替

新物種慢慢地陸續(xù)出現(xiàn)——論其不同的變化速率——物種一旦滅亡即不再出現(xiàn)——出現(xiàn)和消滅時物種群與單一物種所遵循的一般規(guī)律一樣——論滅絕——論全世界生物類型同時發(fā)生變化——滅絕物種相互間及其與現(xiàn)存物種的親緣——論古代類型的發(fā)展狀況——論同一區(qū)域內同一模式的演替——前章和本章提要

現(xiàn)在來看一看,與生物在地質上的演替有關的若干事實和法則,究竟是與物種不變的普通觀點相一致呢,還是與物種通過傳承和自然選擇緩慢地、逐漸地發(fā)生變化的觀點相一致呢。

無論在陸上和水中,新的物種是極其緩慢地陸續(xù)出現(xiàn)的。賴爾曾闡明,第三紀的若干階段里有這方面的證據(jù),這幾乎是不可能加以反對的;而且每年都傾向于把各階段間的空隙填充起來,使滅絕類型與現(xiàn)存類型之間的比例更加成為漸進系統(tǒng)。在某些最近代的巖層里(如果用年來計算,當然確屬極古代的),不過一兩個物種是滅絕了的類型,并且其中只有一兩個新的類型,第一次出現(xiàn),或者是地方性的,或者據(jù)我們所知,是遍于地球表面的。如果信任西西里島菲利皮(Philippi)的觀察,該島海水生物有許多連續(xù)的變化,但是循序漸進。第二紀地質層是比較間斷的;但據(jù)勃龍說,埋藏在各層里的許多滅絕物種的出現(xiàn)和消滅都不是同時的。

不同綱和不同屬的物種,并沒有按照同一速率或同一程度發(fā)生變化。在最古老的第三紀層里,在大批滅絕的類型中還可以找見少數(shù)現(xiàn)存的貝類。福爾克納曾就同樣事實舉出過一個顯著例子,喜馬拉雅山下的沉積物中有一種現(xiàn)存的鱷魚與許多消滅了的奇怪哺乳類和爬行類在一起。志留紀的海豆芽與本屬的現(xiàn)存物種差異很??;然而志留紀的大多數(shù)其他軟體動物和所有甲殼類已經(jīng)大變了。陸棲生物似乎比海棲生物變得快,瑞士最近觀察到了這種動人的例子。有理由相信,高等生物比低等生物的變得要快得多,盡管這一規(guī)律是有例外的。按照匹克推特的說法,生物的變化量并不嚴格對應于地質層的演替,所以兩個連續(xù)地質層之間生物類型的變化程度很少是一模一樣的。然而,如果我們只把密切關聯(lián)的地質層比較一下,可發(fā)現(xiàn)一切物種都進行過某種變化。如果一個物種一度從地球表面上消失,有理由相信同樣的類型不會再出現(xiàn)。只有巴蘭德所謂的“殖民動物”對于后一規(guī)律是一個極明顯的例外,在一個時期內侵入到較古的地質層里,于是使既往生存的動物群又重新出現(xiàn);但賴爾的解釋似乎可以令人滿意,他說這是從斷然不同的地理區(qū)域來的暫時移民的個案。

這些事實與我的理論很一致。我不贊成一成不變的發(fā)展定律,讓一個地域內所有生物都突然地、同時地,或者同等程度地發(fā)生變化。變異的過程一定是極緩慢的。各物種的變異性與所有其他物種沒有依賴。至于這種變異是否會通過自然選擇而得到利用,是否好歹被積累起來,因而引起變異物種或多或少的變異量,則取決于許多復雜的偶發(fā)事件——取決于具有有利性質的變異、互交力量、繁育速度、當?shù)鼐徛兓奈锢項l件,特別是與變化著的物種相競爭的其他生物的性質。因此,毫不奇怪,某一物種保持相同形態(tài)比其他物種長久得多;或者,縱有變化,也變化得較少。我們在地理分布上看到了同樣的情況,例如,馬德拉的陸棲貝類和鞘翅類昆蟲,與歐洲大陸上的最近親緣差異很大,而海棲貝類和鳥類卻沒有改變。根據(jù)前章所說,高等生物對于有機和無機的生活條件有著更為復雜的關系,我們大概就能理解陸棲生物和高等生物比海棲生物和低等生物的變化速度顯然要快得多。當任何地區(qū)的許多生物已經(jīng)變異和改進,我們根據(jù)競爭的原理以及生物與生物間許多重大關系的原理,就能理解不曾在某種程度上發(fā)生變異和改進的任何類型都易于被消滅。因此,我們如果觀察足夠長的間隔時間,就可以明白為什么同一個地方的一切物種終究都要變異,因為不變異就要歸于滅絕。

同綱的各成員在長久而相等期間內的平均變化量也許近乎相同;但是,富含化石的、持續(xù)久遠的地質層的堆積有賴于沉積物在沉陷地域的大量沉積,所以現(xiàn)在的地質層幾乎必須在廣大的、不規(guī)則的間歇期間內堆積起來;結果,埋藏在連續(xù)地質層內的化石所顯示的有機變化量就不相等了。按照這一觀點,每個地質層并不標志著一出神創(chuàng)論的新戲,而不過是節(jié)奏緩慢的戲劇里隨便拉出的一個場景罷了。

我們能夠清楚理解,為什么物種一旦滅亡了,縱使有完全一樣的有機無機的生活條件再出現(xiàn),也決不會再出現(xiàn)了。因為物種的后代雖然可以在自然組成中適應并且占據(jù)另一物種的確切位置(這種情形無疑曾無數(shù)次發(fā)生),從而把它淘汰掉;但是新舊兩個類型不會完全相同,幾乎肯定都從各自不同的祖先遺傳了不同的性狀。例如,如果扇尾鴿都毀滅了,養(yǎng)鴿者長期努力復原,可能育出一個和現(xiàn)有品種很難區(qū)別的新品種來。但原種巖鴿如果也同樣被毀滅掉,我們有充分理由相信,在自然狀況下,親類型一般要被改進了的后代所淘汰消滅,于是,就很難相信與現(xiàn)存品種相同的扇尾鴿,能從任何其他鴿種,甚至從任何其他十分穩(wěn)定的家鴿族育出來,因為新形成的扇尾鴿幾乎肯定會從新祖先那里遺傳某種輕微不同的性狀。

物種群,即屬和科,在出現(xiàn)和消滅上所遵循的一般規(guī)律與單一物種相同,變化有緩急,程度也有大小。一個群,一經(jīng)消滅就永不再現(xiàn);也就是說,它的生存無論延續(xù)到多久,總是連續(xù)的。我知道這一規(guī)律有幾個顯著的例外,但例外少得驚人,連福布斯、匹克推特和伍德沃德(雖然都堅決反對我所持的觀點)都承認這個規(guī)律的正確性。而且這一規(guī)律與我的理論是嚴格一致的。因為同群的所有物種都是從一個物種傳下來的,很明顯只要該群的任何物種在漫長的時代中出現(xiàn),其成員就必定延續(xù)到那么久,以便產(chǎn)生變異新種或者未變異舊類型。例如,海豆芽屬的物種,必定連續(xù)存在,形成一條連綿不斷的世代系列,從下志留紀地層直到今天。

上一章里看到,物種的全群有時會呈現(xiàn)一種假象,好似突然出現(xiàn)的;我試著提出了一種解釋,如果正確,對我的觀點會是致命傷。但是這種個案確是例外;一般規(guī)律是物種群逐漸增加數(shù)目,一旦增加到極大值,又遲早要逐漸減少。如果一個屬里的物種數(shù),一個科里的屬數(shù)目,用粗細不同的一條豎線來表示,穿越發(fā)現(xiàn)物種的連續(xù)地質層,則豎線有時虛假地表現(xiàn)為在下端起始,并不是尖銳的點,而是突然露頭;隨后豎線向上加粗,同一粗度常??梢员3忠欢尉嚯x,最后在上層巖床中變細消失,表示此物種減少,最后滅絕。一個群的物種數(shù)的這種逐漸增加,與我的理論是嚴格合拍的。因為同屬的物種和同科的屬只能緩慢地、累進地增加;變異的過程和一些近似類型的產(chǎn)生必然是緩慢漸進的過程——一個物種先產(chǎn)生兩三個變種,再慢慢地轉變成物種,又以同樣緩慢的步驟產(chǎn)生別的物種,如此下去,就像一株大樹從一條樹干上抽出許多分枝一樣,直到變成大群。

論滅絕?!链宋覀冎皇歉綆д劦搅宋锓N和物種群的消失。根據(jù)自然選擇學說,舊類型的滅絕與改進的新類型的產(chǎn)生是有密切關系的。認為地球上一切生物在連續(xù)時代內被災變一掃而光的舊觀念,已被普遍拋棄了,就連埃利·德·博蒙(Elie de Beaumont)、默奇森、巴蘭德等地質學者也在內,他們的一般觀點會自然地引導他們達成這種結論。另一方面,根據(jù)對第三紀地質層的研究,我們有充分理由相信,物種和物種群先從一地,然后從又一地,終于從全世界挨次地、逐漸地消滅。單一的物種也好,物種的全群也好,它們的延續(xù)期間都極不相等:如我們所見到的,有些群從已知的生命曙光時代起一直延續(xù)到今,而有些群在古生代結束之前就消滅了。似乎沒有一條定律可以決定任何一個物種、屬能夠延續(xù)多長時期。有理由相信,物種全群的消滅過程一般要比產(chǎn)生過程為慢;如果出現(xiàn)和消滅照前面所講的用粗細不同的豎線來表示,可見表示滅絕進程線的上端的變細,要比表示初次出現(xiàn)和物種數(shù)增多的下端來得緩慢,然而,在某些情形里,全群的滅絕曾經(jīng)奇怪地突然發(fā)生了,例如接近第二紀末的菊石。

物種滅絕的整個主題搞得撲朔迷離,真是莫名其妙。有些作者甚至假定,物種就像個體有一定的壽命那樣有一定的存續(xù)期。大概不會有人像我那樣曾對物種的滅絕感到如此驚奇。我驚訝地在拉普拉塔發(fā)現(xiàn)乳齒象(Mastodon)、大懶獸(Megatherium)、箭齒獸(Toxodon)等滅絕怪物的遺骸中嵌著馬齒,它們在最近的地質時代曾與今日依然生存的貝類一起共存。鑒于自從馬被西班牙人引進南美洲以后,就在全境變成為野生的,且以無比的速率增加數(shù)量,我問自己,在這樣分明極其有利的生活條件下,是什么東西把以前的馬在這樣近的時代消滅了呢。但是我的驚奇是毫無根據(jù)的!歐文教授即刻看出,牙齒雖然與現(xiàn)存的馬齒如此相像,卻屬于滅絕的馬種,如果這種馬至今依然存在,只是稀少些,任何學者對于此一點也不會感到驚奇;因為稀少現(xiàn)象是所有地方所有綱里的大多數(shù)物種的屬性。如果我們自問,為什么這一物種或那個物種會稀少呢?可以回答,生活條件有些不利;但是,哪些不利呢,不得而知。假定化石馬至今仍作為稀少物種存在,我們根據(jù)與所有其他哺乳動物(甚至包括繁殖率低的象)的類比,根據(jù)家養(yǎng)馬在南美洲的歸化歷史,肯定會感到在更有利的條件下,它一定會在很少幾年內布滿整個大陸。但是我們無法說出抑制它增加的不利條件是什么,是由于某種偶然事故呢,還是由于幾種偶然事故?也不知馬一生中的什么年齡,在什么程度上這些生活條件各自發(fā)生作用的。如果條件轉向不利,不管如何緩慢,我們確實不會覺察出,然而化石馬必定漸漸地稀少,而終至滅絕——于是它的地位便被成功的競爭者取而代之。

實在很難始終記住,各種生物的增加,不斷受到察覺不到的敵對作用的抑制;而且其作用完全足以使它稀少,以致最后滅絕。更近的第三紀地質層里,看到許多先稀少而后滅絕的情形;我們知道,通過人為的作用,一些動物之局部或全部的滅絕過程,也是一樣的。我愿意重復一下我在1845年發(fā)表的文章,認為物種一般是先稀少,然后滅絕——對于物種的稀少并不感到奇怪,而當物種滅絕卻大感驚異,這就好像認為病是死的前驅一樣——對于病并不感到奇怪,而對病人死去卻感到驚異,以致懷疑他是死于未知暴力一樣。

自然選擇學說的根據(jù)是,各個新變種,最終是各個新物種,由于比競爭者占有某種優(yōu)勢而產(chǎn)生和保持下來;較為不利類型的最終滅絕,幾乎是不可避免的結果。家養(yǎng)生物也同樣,新的稍微改進的變種培育出來,首先就要淘汰掉同地塊改進較少的變種;當它大有改進,就會像我們的短角牛那樣被運送到遠近各地,并在他處取其他品種的地位而代之。這樣,新類型的出現(xiàn)和舊類型的消失,不論是自然產(chǎn)生還是人工產(chǎn)生的,就聯(lián)結在一起了。在某些繁盛的群里,一定時間內產(chǎn)生的新物種類型的數(shù)目,大概要比滅絕的舊物種類型為多;但是我們知道,物種并不是無限繼續(xù)增加的,至少在最近的地質時代內是如此,所以,注意一下晚近的時代,我們就可以相信,新類型的產(chǎn)生引起了差不多同樣數(shù)目的舊類型的滅絕。

如同前面解釋過的和實例說明過的那樣,在各方面彼此最相像的類型之間,競爭也一般最為劇烈。因此,改進和變異的后代一般會招致親種的滅絕;而且,如果許多新類型是從任何一個物種發(fā)展起來的,那么這個物種的最近親緣,即同屬的物種最易滅絕。因此,我相信,一物種傳下來的若干新物種,即新屬,終于會淘汰同科的一個舊屬。但也屢屢有這樣的情形,即某一群的一個新物種奪取了別群的一個物種的地位,因而招致它的滅絕。如果許多近似類型是從成功的侵入者發(fā)展起來的,勢必有許多類型要讓出地位;被消滅的通常是近似類型,一般由于共同遺傳了某種劣性而受到損害。但是,讓位給其他變異和改進物種的那些物種,無論是屬于同綱或異綱,總還有少數(shù)可以保存一個長久時間,因為適于某些特別的生活方式,或者因為棲息在遠離、孤立的地方,從而逃避了劇烈的競爭。例如,三角蛤屬(Trigonia)是第二紀地質層里的貝類大屬,其一個物種還殘存在澳洲的海里,而且硬鱗魚類(Ganoid)這個幾乎滅絕的大群中的少數(shù)成員,至今還棲息在我們的淡水里。所以我們看到,物種群的徹底滅絕要比產(chǎn)生過程緩慢。

關于全科或全目的明顯突然滅絕,如古生代末的三葉蟲和第二紀末的菊石,我們必須記住前面已經(jīng)說過的情形,即在連續(xù)的地質層之間大概間隔著廣闊的時間,期間可能發(fā)生了大批很緩慢的滅絕。還有,如果一個新群的許多物種,由于突然的移入,或者異常迅猛的發(fā)展,而占據(jù)了一個新地區(qū),那么,許多的舊物種就會以相應快的速度滅絕。這樣讓出地位的類型普遍都是那些近似類型,因為共同具有某種劣性。

因此,在我看來,單一物種以及物種全群的滅絕方式是與自然選擇學說十分合拍的。我們對于物種滅絕不必驚異;一定要驚異的話,還是對我們的自以為是表示驚異吧——一時想象自己理解了決定各個物種生存的許多復雜偶然性。各個物種都有過度增加的傾向,而且有我們很少察覺得出的某種抑制作用常在活動,我們一旦忘記這一點,整個自然組成就會弄得莫名其妙。每當我們能夠確切說明為什么這個物種的個體會比那個物種多;為什么這個物種,而不是那個物種能在某一地方歸化;那么,只有到了那時,才能對于為什么說明不了這一物種或者物種群的滅絕,理所當然地表示驚異。

論全世界生物類型幾乎同時發(fā)生變化。——生物類型在全世界幾乎同時發(fā)生變化,古生物學發(fā)現(xiàn)很少有比這個事實更令人震撼的了。例如,歐洲的白堊層在極不同氣候下,世界許多遙遠地方都能辨識出來,雖然那里沒有發(fā)現(xiàn)一塊白堊礦物,也就是在北美洲,在南美洲赤道地帶,在火地,在好望角,以及在印度半島。在這些遙遠的地方,某些巖層的生物遺骸與白堊生物遺骸呈現(xiàn)了明顯無誤的相似性。見到的并不見得是同一物種,某些情形里沒有一個物種是完全相同的,但它們屬于同科、同屬和亞屬,而且有時僅在細微之點上,如表面上的斑條,具有相似的特性。還有,未曾在歐洲白堊層中發(fā)現(xiàn)的,但在它的上部或下部地質層中出現(xiàn)的其他類型,同樣未出現(xiàn)在世界上的這些遙遠地方。若干作者曾在俄羅斯、西歐和北美的若干連續(xù)的古生代層中觀察到生物類型具有類似的平行現(xiàn)象。按照賴爾的意見,歐洲和北美洲的若干第三紀沉積物也是這樣的。哪怕完全不考慮新舊世界所共有的少數(shù)化石物種,分隔很大的古生代和第三紀時期的歷代生物類型的一般平行現(xiàn)象仍然是顯著的,而且若干地質層的相互關系也容易確立。

然而,這些觀察都是關于世界各地的海棲生物的:我們還沒有充分數(shù)據(jù)可以判斷相隔遙遠的陸棲生物和淡水生物是否也同樣發(fā)生平行的變化。我們可以懷疑它們是否曾經(jīng)這樣變化過:如果把大懶獸、磨齒獸(Mylodon)、長頸駝(Macrauchenia,大弓齒獸)和箭齒獸從拉普拉塔帶到歐洲,而不說明它們的地質信息,大概沒有人會猜測它們曾經(jīng)和依然生存的海棲貝類共同生存過;但是,由于這些異常的怪物曾和乳齒象和馬共同生存過,所以至少可以推論它們曾經(jīng)在第三紀的某一晚近時期內生存過。

說到海棲生物類型曾經(jīng)在全世界同時發(fā)生變化,決不可假定這種說法是指同一千年,同十萬年,也不可假定它有很嚴格的地質學意義;因為,如果把現(xiàn)在生存于歐洲的、曾經(jīng)在更新世(如用年來計算,這是一個包括整個冰期的很遙遠的時期)生存于歐洲的一切海棲動物與現(xiàn)今生存于南美洲、澳洲的海棲動物加以比較,再熟練的學者也很難指出,極其密切類似南半球那些動物的是歐洲的現(xiàn)存動物還是歐洲更新世的動物。還有幾位高明的觀察者主張,美國的現(xiàn)存生物與曾經(jīng)在歐洲第三紀后期的那些生物之間的關系,比它們與歐洲的現(xiàn)存生物之間的關系更為密切;如果屬實,現(xiàn)在沉積于北美洲海岸的化石層,今后顯然會與歐洲較古的化石層歸為一類。然而,如果展望遙遠將來的時代,我看毫無疑問,一切較近代的海成地質層,即歐洲的、南北美洲和澳洲的上新世上層、更新世層以及嚴格的近代層,由于含有多少類似的化石遺骸,由于不含有只見于較古的下層堆積物中的那些類型,在地質學的意義上是可以正確列為同時代的。

在上述的廣義里,生物類型在世界上遠隔的地方同時發(fā)生變化的事實,曾經(jīng)大大地觸動了那些可敬的觀察者,如德韋納伊(MM.de Verneuil)和達爾夏克(d'Archiac)。說過歐洲各地方古生代生物類型的平行現(xiàn)象之后,他們又說:“我們如果被這種奇異的序列所觸動,而把注意力轉向北美洲,并且在那里發(fā)現(xiàn)一系列的類似現(xiàn)象,那么可以肯定所有這些物種的變異滅絕,以及新物種的出現(xiàn),決不能僅僅看海流的變化或多少局部和暫時的他種原因,而是依據(jù)支配整個動物界的一般法則?!卑吞m德先生曾經(jīng)有力地說出大意完全相同的話。把海流、氣候等物理條件的變化,看作是處于極其不同氣候下的全世界生物類型發(fā)生這等大變化的原因,誠然是太無聊了。正如巴蘭德所指出的,我們必須看某一特殊法則。如果我們討論到生物的現(xiàn)在分布情形,看到各地方的物理條件與生物本性之間的關系是何等淡薄,會更清楚地理解這一點。

全世界生物類型平行演替這一重大事實,可用自然選擇學說解釋。新物種由于對較老的類型占有優(yōu)勢的新變種興起而形成;在本地區(qū)已占上風、比其他類型占有某種優(yōu)勢的類型,自然會產(chǎn)生最多的新變種,即初始物種。初始物種必須更大程度地成功,才能得到保存,得以生存。我們在占有優(yōu)勢的植物中可以找到關于這一問題的明證,即在原產(chǎn)地最普通的而且分散最廣的植物,會產(chǎn)生最大數(shù)目的新變種。占有優(yōu)勢、變異著而且分布遼闊,并在某種范圍內已經(jīng)侵入到其他物種領域的物種,當然一定具有最好機會進一步拓展,在新地區(qū)產(chǎn)生新變種和物種。分散的過程,常常是很緩慢的,取決于氣候和地理的變化,要取決于意外的偶然事件。但是,從長遠的觀點看,占有優(yōu)勢的類型一般會在拓展上成功。在分離的大陸上,陸棲生物的分散也許要比連接的海洋中的海棲生物來得緩慢些。可以預料,陸棲生物演替中的平行現(xiàn)象,其程度不如海棲生物那樣嚴密,而我們看到的也確是如此。

優(yōu)勢物種從任何區(qū)域拓展開來,可能遭遇更多的優(yōu)勢物種,那么它們的勝利道路,乃至生存就會止步。我們并不精確了解新優(yōu)勢物種繁殖的全部有利條件是什么,但我想可以看到,一批個體給了有利變異出現(xiàn)的更好機會,且與許多現(xiàn)有類型的激烈競爭會非常有利,還有拓展到新領地的力量也有利。一定的隔離量在很長的間隔時間后重現(xiàn),也許也是有利的,如前所述。世界上一個區(qū)域也許對于陸棲新優(yōu)勢物種的產(chǎn)生最為有利,另一個區(qū)域則對于海水新優(yōu)勢物種最為有利。假如兩個大地區(qū)長期處于同等程度的有利環(huán)境,其中的生物遭遇時,戰(zhàn)斗會曠日持久而慘烈。一個棲息地的某些物種和另一個棲息地的一些物種會勝利。但是,從長遠看,優(yōu)勢最大的類型不管出自何方,傾向于全面勝利。勝利后會引起其他的劣勢類型的滅絕。由于劣勢類型一般通過遺傳而結成親緣群體,所以整群的物種會日漸消失,當然單一的成員能夠在零星地區(qū)長久生存。

這樣,在我看來,全世界同樣生物類型的平行演替,就其廣義來說,它們的同時演替,與新物種由于優(yōu)勢物種的廣為拓展和變異而形成這一原理非常符合:這樣產(chǎn)生的新物種本身有遺傳優(yōu)勢,而且已經(jīng)比親種和其他物種具有某種優(yōu)越性,并且將進一步拓展、變異產(chǎn)生新物種。被擊敗而讓位給新的勝利者的類型,由于共同地遺傳了某種劣性,一般都是親緣的群;所以,當改進的新群分布于全世界時,老群就會從世上消失;而且各地類型的演替,在最初出現(xiàn)和最后消失方面都傾向于一致。

還有與這個問題相關的另一值得注意之點。我已經(jīng)提出理由表示相信:大多數(shù)富含化石的巨大地質層,是在沉降期間沉積下來的;不具化石的空白極長的間隔,發(fā)生在海底的靜止或者隆起時,同樣也在沉積物的沉積速度不足以淹沒和保存生物的遺骸時出現(xiàn)。在這長久的空白間隔時期,我想各地的生物都曾經(jīng)歷了相當量的變異和滅絕,而且從世界的其他地方進行了大量的遷徙。有理由相信,廣大地面曾蒙受同一運動的影響,所以嚴格同時代的地質層,大概往往是在世界同一部分的廣闊空間內堆積起來的;但我們決沒有權利斷定這是一成不變的情形,而且廣大地面總是不變地要受同一運動的影響。當兩個地質層在兩處地方于幾乎一樣的、但并不完全一樣的期間內沉積下來時,按照前節(jié)所講的理由,這兩種情形中應該看到生物類型中相同的一般演替;但是物種不會是完全一致的,因為對于變異、滅絕和遷徙,這一地方比那一地方會有稍微多點的時間。

我猜想歐洲是有這種情形的。普雷斯特維奇(Prestwich)先生關于英法兩國始新世沉積物的可稱贊的論文,曾在兩國的連續(xù)諸層之間找出了嚴密的一般平行現(xiàn)象;但是把英法兩國的某些階段加以比較時,雖然他看出兩地同屬的物種數(shù)目非常一致,然而物種本身卻有差異,除非假定有地峽把兩個海分開,分別棲息著同時代的但不相同的動物群,否則從兩國接近這一點來考慮,此差異實難解釋。賴爾對某些第三紀后期的地質層也做過相似的觀察。巴蘭德也指出波希米亞和斯堪的納維亞的連續(xù)的志留紀沉積物之間有著顯著的一般平行現(xiàn)象;不過,他還是看出了那些物種之間有著驚人的差異量。如果這些地方的地質層不是在完全相同的時期內沉積下來的——某一地的地質層往往相當于另一地的空白間隔——而且,如果兩地物種是在若干地質層的堆積期間和它們之間的長久間隔期間徐徐進行變化的;那么在這種情形下,兩地方的若干地質層按照生物類型的一般演替,可以排列為同一順序,因而會虛假地呈現(xiàn)出嚴格的平行現(xiàn)象;盡管如此,物種在兩地方的外觀相當?shù)闹T層中并不見得是完全相同的。

論滅絕物種之間的親緣及其與現(xiàn)存類型的親緣?!F(xiàn)在讓我們考察一下滅絕物種與現(xiàn)存物種的相互親緣。它們都可歸入一個自然大系統(tǒng);這一事實根據(jù)傳承的原理即可得到解釋。任何類型越古老,一般與現(xiàn)存類型之間的差異便越大。但是,巴克蘭(Buckland)早就闡明,化石都可以分類在至今還生存的群里,或者分類在這些群之間。滅絕的生物類型可以有助于填滿現(xiàn)存的屬、科和目之間的巨大間隔,這一點毋庸置疑。如果我們單單關注現(xiàn)存物種或滅絕物種,則其系列的完整就遠不如把兩者合在一個系統(tǒng)中。至于脊椎動物,古生物學家歐文可以用精彩的插圖填滿很多頁,顯示滅絕動物介于現(xiàn)存群之間。居維葉曾把反芻類(Ruminants)和厚皮類(Pachyderms)排列為哺乳動物中最不相同的兩個目;但是歐文發(fā)現(xiàn)了眾多的化石環(huán)節(jié),他不得不改變全部兩個目的分類法,而把某些厚皮類與反芻類一齊放在同一個亞目中。例如,他根據(jù)細微級進取消了豬與駱駝之間明顯的大差別。至于無脊椎動物,無比權威的巴蘭德說,他每日都領悟到,雖然古生代的動物同屬于現(xiàn)存的目、科、屬里,但在這樣古老的時代,各群并不像現(xiàn)在一樣區(qū)別得那么清楚。

有些作者反對把任何滅絕物種或物種群看作是現(xiàn)存物種或物種群之間的中間物。如果這個術語是指滅絕類型在一切性狀上都是直接介于兩個現(xiàn)存類型之間的話,這種反對或許是正當?shù)?。但是在自然的分類里,我發(fā)覺許多化石物種的確處于現(xiàn)存物種中間,而且某些滅絕屬處于現(xiàn)存屬中間,甚至處于異科的屬中間。最普通的情形似乎是(特別是差異很大的群,如魚類和爬行類),假定它們今日是由十二個性狀來區(qū)別的,則古代成員賴以區(qū)別的性狀會較少,所以這兩個群以前多少要比今日更為接近些。

常言道,類型越古老,其某些性狀就越能把現(xiàn)在區(qū)別很大的群連接起來。這句話無疑只限于在地質時代中曾經(jīng)發(fā)生巨大變化的那些群;可是要證明這種主張的正確性卻是困難的,因為,甚至現(xiàn)存動物,如肺魚,已發(fā)現(xiàn)常常與很不相同的群有親緣關系。然而,如果我們把古代的爬行類和無尾兩棲類、古代的魚類、古代的頭足類以及始新世的哺乳類,與各該綱的較近代成員加以比較時,必須承認這句話是有一定道理的。

讓我們看一看這幾種事實和推論與變異傳承學說的符合程度。這個問題有些復雜,必須請讀者回顧第四章的圖解。設有數(shù)字字母代表屬,它們那里分出來的虛線代表每一屬的物種。這圖解過于簡單,列出來的屬和物種太少,不過沒關系。橫線代表連續(xù)的地質層,最上橫線以下的一切類型都看作已滅絕。三個現(xiàn)存屬,a14,q14,p14形成一個小科;b14,f14是一個密切近似的科或亞科;o14,e14,m14是第三個科。這三個科和從親類型A分出來的幾條傳承線上的許多滅絕屬合起來成為一個目,都從古代原始共同祖先遺傳了某些相同的東西。根據(jù)以前這個圖解說明的性狀不斷分歧傾向的原理,任何類型越是近代,一般越與原始祖先不同。這樣,我們對最古化石與現(xiàn)存類型之間差異最大這個規(guī)律便可了解。然而,我們決不可假定性狀分歧是必然發(fā)生的偶然性;它完全取決于物種的后代由此能夠在自然組成中攫取許多的、不同的地位。所以,物種很可能隨著生活條件的稍微改變而繼續(xù)略微改變,并且在極長的時期內還保持著同樣的一般特性,如同我們見到的某些志留紀類型的情形。這種情形在圖解中用f14來表示。

如前,所有從A傳下來的眾多類型,無論是滅絕的和現(xiàn)存的,形成一個目;這一個目由于滅絕和性狀分歧的連續(xù)影響,便分為若干亞科和科,其中有些假定已在不同的時期內滅亡了,有些卻一直存續(xù)到今天。

考察圖解便可看出,假定埋藏在連續(xù)地質層中的許多滅絕類型如果是在這個系列的下方幾個點上發(fā)現(xiàn)的,那么最上線的三個現(xiàn)存科的彼此差異就會小一些。例如,如果a1,a5,a10,f8,m3,m6,m9等屬被發(fā)掘出來,那三個科就會十分密切地聯(lián)結在一起,大概勢必會連合成一個大科,這與反芻類和厚皮類的情形差不多一樣。然而反對把滅絕屬看作是聯(lián)結起三個科現(xiàn)存屬的中間物的人也有道理,因為它們成為中間物并不是直接的,卻是通過許多大不相同的類型,經(jīng)過漫長曲折的路程。如果許多滅絕類型是在中央的橫線地質層之一——例如VI號線——之上發(fā)現(xiàn)的,而且線下什么也沒有,那么只有左邊兩個科(a14等和b14等)勢必合而為一;另外兩個科(a14到f14現(xiàn)在包括五個屬,還有o14到m14)還是會保持不同。然而,這兩個科的相互差異要比化石發(fā)現(xiàn)以前來得小些。例如,設兩個科的現(xiàn)存屬彼此相差十二個性狀,那么在VI橫線那個時代生存的各屬,相差的性狀就要少一些;因為在傳承的這樣早期階段,從本目共同祖先的性狀分歧沒有以后程度大。這樣,古老而滅絕的屬往往在性狀上便好歹介于它們的變異后代之間,或介于旁系親族之間。

在自然狀況下,情況要比圖解所示的復雜得多;群的數(shù)目更多,存續(xù)的時間極端不等,而且變異的程度也不相同。我們所掌握的不過是地質記錄的最后一卷,而且殘缺不全,除極少的情況下,我們沒有權利指望把自然系統(tǒng)中的廣大間隔填充起來,從而把不同的科目聯(lián)結起來。我們所能期望的,只是那些在既知地質時期中曾經(jīng)發(fā)生過巨大變異的群,應該在較古的地質層里彼此稍微接近些;所以較古的成員要比同群的現(xiàn)存成員在某些性狀上的彼此差異來得小些;最優(yōu)秀古生物學者們一致證明,情形常常是這樣。

這樣,根據(jù)變異傳承學說,有關滅絕生物類型彼此之間,及其與現(xiàn)存類型之間的相互親緣關系的主要事實似乎可得到圓滿解釋,而用其他任何觀點是完全解釋不通的。

根據(jù)同一學說,很明顯,地球歷史上任何一個大時期內的動物群,在一般性狀上將承前啟后。例如,生存在圖解第六個大時期的物種,是生存在第五個時期的物種的變異后代,而且是第七個時期更加變異了的物種的祖先;因此,它們在性狀上幾乎不會不是介于上下生物類型之間的。然而,必須承認,某些以前的類型已經(jīng)全部滅絕,而且任何地方都有新類型從外地移入,在連續(xù)地質層之間的長久空白間隔時期曾發(fā)生過大量變異。有鑒于此,每一個地質時代的動物群在性狀上無疑是介于前后動物群之間的。這里只要舉出一個事例就可以了。當泥盆系最初發(fā)現(xiàn)時,這個系的化石立刻被學者們認為在性狀上是介于上層的石炭系和下層的志留系之間的。但是,各動物群并不一定完全介于中間,因為連續(xù)的地質層中有不等的間隔時間。

各時代的動物群從整體上看,在性狀上是近乎承前啟后的,某些屬對于這一規(guī)律雖為例外,但不足以構成異議以動搖此說正確性。例如,福爾克納博士曾把乳齒象和象按照兩種分類法進行排列——先按照互相親緣,再按照生存時代,結果兩者并不符合。具有極端性狀的物種不是最古老的或最近代的;具有中間性狀的物種也不是屬于中間時代的。但是在這種以及在其他類似的情形里,如果暫時假定物種的初次出現(xiàn)和消滅的記錄是完全的,我們沒有理由去相信連續(xù)產(chǎn)生的各種類型必定有對應的存續(xù)時間。一個極古的類型可能有時比外地后生的類型存續(xù)得更為長久,棲息在隔離區(qū)域內的陸棲生物尤其如此。以小喻大,如果把家鴿的主要現(xiàn)存族和滅絕族盡可能按照親緣的系列加以排列,則這種排列不會與其產(chǎn)生的時間順序密切一致,而且與其消滅的順序更不一致:親種巖鴿至今還生存著,而許多介于巖鴿和傳書鴿之間的變種已經(jīng)滅絕了;在喙長這一主要性狀上站在極端的傳書鴿,比站在這一系列相反一端的短嘴翻飛鴿發(fā)生更早。

來自中間地質層的生物遺骸在某種程度上具有中間的性狀,與這種說法密切關聯(lián)的有一個事實,是古生物學者都主張的,即兩個連續(xù)地質層的化石彼此之間的關系,遠比兩個遠隔的地質層更為密切。匹克推特舉了一個熟知的事例:來自白堊層的幾個階段的生物遺骸一般是類似的,雖然各個階段中的物種不同。僅僅這一事實,由于它的一般性,似乎已經(jīng)動搖了匹克推特教授物種不變的信念。凡是熟知地球上現(xiàn)存物種分布的人,對于密切連續(xù)地質層中不同物種的密切類似性,不會企圖用古代地域的物理條件保持近乎一樣的說法去解釋的。請記住,生物類型,至少是棲息海里的生物類型,曾經(jīng)在全世界幾乎同時發(fā)生變化,所以變化是在極其不同的氣候和條件下進行的。試想更新世包含著整個冰期,氣候的變化非常之大,請注意海棲生物的物種類型所受到的影響卻是何等之小。

密切連續(xù)地質層中的化石遺骸雖然列為不同的物種,但密切相似,其全部意義根據(jù)生物傳承學說是顯而易見的。因為各地質層的累積往往中斷,并且連續(xù)地質層之間存在著長久的空白間隔,如前章闡明,我們不該期望在任何一兩個地質層中找到在這些時期開始和終了時出現(xiàn)的物種之間的一切中間變種;但是我們在間隔的時間(用年來計量是很長久的,用地質年代來計量則并不長久)之后,應該找到密切近似的類型,即某些作者所謂的代表種;而且我們確能找到。總之,正如我們有權利所期望的那樣,我們已經(jīng)找到證據(jù)來證明物種類型的緩慢的、難覺察的變異。

論古代生物類型的發(fā)展狀態(tài)。——許多人在討論,新近類型是否比古代更發(fā)達。我不想進入這個主題,因為學者們尚未有令對方滿意的關于高級、低級類型的定義。但是,在一個意義上,我的理論認定新近的類型勢必比古代的類型高級;每一個新物種都通過生活斗爭中對先前的類型具有某種優(yōu)勢而形成。如果世界某地始新世的生物與同地或異地現(xiàn)存的生物在幾乎相似的氣候下進行競爭,始新世的動植物當然要敗北消滅;正如第二紀的動物要被始新世的動物打敗消滅,古生代的動物要被第二紀的動物所打敗消滅一樣。我不懷疑,相對于古代失敗類型而言,這種提高過程明顯可察覺地影響到了新近取勝的生命類型的體制,但我找不到測試這種進步的辦法。例如,甲殼類在自己的綱里并不是最高級的,但能打敗軟體動物中最高級的。歐洲的生物近年來以非常之勢擴張到新西蘭,并且奪取了先前被占據(jù)的地方,據(jù)此我們認為,如果把大不列顛的所有動植物都放生到新西蘭去,一大堆英國的生物類型會隨著時間的推移在那里徹底歸化,而且消滅許多土著的類型。另一方面,從新西蘭現(xiàn)在發(fā)生的現(xiàn)象看,鑒于很少有一種南半球的生物曾在歐洲的任何部分變?yōu)橐吧?,如果把新西蘭的一切生物放生到大不列顛去,我們很可懷疑是否會有大量的品種成功奪取現(xiàn)在被英國動植物占據(jù)著的地方。從這種觀點來看,可以說大不列顛的生物要比新西蘭的生物高級得多了。然而最熟練的博物學者,根據(jù)兩地物種的調查,并不能預見到這種結果。

阿加西斯堅決主張,古代動物在某種程度上類似于同綱的新近動物的胚胎,也即滅絕類型在地質上的演替與新近類型的胚胎發(fā)育有一點平行。我必須聽從匹克推特和赫胥黎的想法,認為這種觀點對不對遠未證明。但我滿心希望日后能夠證實,至少是關于從屬群方面的,這些群在新近的時期內相互分枝了。阿加西斯的這個學說與自然選擇論不謀而合。下面章節(jié)將試圖說明成體和胚胎的差異是由于變異在一個不很早的時期發(fā)生,而在相應年齡得到遺傳的緣故。這種過程聽任胚胎幾乎保持不變,同時使成體在連續(xù)的世代中繼續(xù)不斷地增加差異。

因此胚胎好像是自然界保留下來的一張圖畫,描繪著動物先前未大事變化過的狀態(tài)。這種觀點大概是正確的,然而也許永遠得不到充分證明。例如,最古的已知哺乳類、爬行類和魚類都嚴格地屬于它們的本綱,雖然它們之中有些老類型彼此之間的差異比今日同群的典型成員彼此之間的差異稍少,但要想找尋具有脊椎動物共同胚胎特性的動物大概是徒勞的,除非志留紀地層的最下部以下深處發(fā)現(xiàn)巖床,但發(fā)現(xiàn)這種地層的機會是很少的。

第三紀末期同一地域內同樣模式的演替?!S多年前,克利夫特(Clift)先生曾闡明,從澳洲洞穴內找到的化石哺乳動物與該洲的現(xiàn)存有袋類是密切近似的。南美洲拉普拉塔的若干地方發(fā)現(xiàn)的類似犰狳甲片的巨大甲片中,同樣的關系也是顯著的,外行人也可以看出。歐文教授曾以最動人的方式闡明,在拉普拉塔埋藏的大量化石哺乳動物,大多數(shù)與南美洲的模式有關系。倫德(MM.Lund)和克勞森(Clausen)在巴西洞穴里采集的豐富化石骨中,可以更明白地看到這種關系。這等事實給我的印象極深,便在1839年和1845年堅決主張這種“模式演替的法則”和“同一大陸上死亡者和生存者之間的奇妙關系”。歐文教授后來把這種概念擴展到歐洲大陸的哺乳動物上去。在這位作者復制的新西蘭滅絕巨型鳥中,我們看到同樣的法則。巴西洞穴的鳥類中也可看到同樣的法則。伍德沃德教授曾闡明,同樣的法則對于海棲貝類也是適用的,但是由于大多數(shù)軟體動物分布廣闊,所以并沒有很好地表現(xiàn)出來。還可舉出其他的例子,如馬德拉的滅絕陸棲貝類與現(xiàn)存陸棲貝類之間的關系,以及咸海里海(Aralo-Caspian)的滅絕與現(xiàn)存堿水貝類之間的關系。

那么,同一地域內同一模式的演替這個重要法則意味著什么呢?如果有人把同緯度下澳洲和南美洲某些地方的現(xiàn)存氣候加以比較之后,就企圖以不同的物理條件來解釋這兩個大陸上生物的不同,而另一方面又以相同的條件來解釋第三紀末期兩個大陸上同一模式的一致,那么,他可算是大膽了。也不能斷言有袋類主要或僅僅產(chǎn)于澳洲,貧齒類以及其他美洲模式的動物僅僅產(chǎn)于南美洲,是不變的法則。因為我們知道,古代歐洲曾有許多有袋類動物棲住過;我在上述出版物中曾闡明美洲陸棲哺乳類的分布法則,從前不同于現(xiàn)在。從前北美洲非常具有該大陸南半部分的特性;南半部分從前也比今天更為密切近似北半部分。同樣,根據(jù)福爾克納和考特利(Cautley)的發(fā)現(xiàn),我們知道印度北部的哺乳動物,從前比今天更為密切近似非洲。關于海棲動物的分布,也可以舉出類似的事實來。

按照變異傳承學說,同一地域內同樣模式持久地但并非不變地演替這一偉大法則,便立刻得到說明;因為世界各地的生物,在以后連續(xù)的時間內,顯然都傾向于把密切近似而又有某種程度變異的后代遺留在該地。如果一個大陸上的生物從前曾與另一大陸差異很大,那么它們的變異后代仍然會按照近乎同樣的方式和程度發(fā)生差異。但是經(jīng)過了很長的間隔期間以后,同時經(jīng)過了容許大量互相遷徙的巨大地理變化以后,較弱的類型會讓位給占優(yōu)勢的類型,而生物過去和現(xiàn)在的分布法則就不會一成不變了。

有人會嘲笑著問,我是否曾假定大懶獸以及親緣大怪物在南美洲遺留了樹懶、犰狳和食蟻獸作為退化的后代?這是完全不能承認的。這種巨大動物全部滅絕了,沒留下后代。但巴西的洞穴內有許多滅絕物種在大小和其他性狀上與南美洲現(xiàn)存物種密切近似;這等化石中的某些物種也許是現(xiàn)存物種的真實祖先。千萬不要忘記,按照我的理論,同屬的一切物種都是某一物種的后代,所以,如果有各具八物種的六個屬見于一個地質層中,而且有六個具有同樣八物種的其他親緣或代表的屬見于后面連續(xù)的地層中,那么,我們可以斷言,各個較老的屬只有一個物種留下了變異后代,構成六個新屬,各個老屬的其他七個物種皆歸滅亡,沒有留下后代。還有更普通的情形,即六個老屬中只有兩三個屬的兩三個物種是六個新屬的雙親:其他老物種和其他老屬全歸滅絕。在衰微的目里,如南美洲的貧齒類,屬和物種的數(shù)目都在減少,所以只有更少的屬和物種能留下變異的嫡系后代。

前章和本章提要?!以噲D闡明,地質記錄是極端不完全的;地球只有一小部分做過細密地質學調查,只有某些綱的生物在化石狀態(tài)下大都保存下來;博物館里保存的標本和物種的數(shù)目,即使與區(qū)區(qū)一個地質層中所經(jīng)歷的世代數(shù)相比也完全等于零。由于沉陷對富含化石而且厚到足以經(jīng)受未來陵削作用的沉積物的累積是必要的,連續(xù)地質層之間必有長久的間隔期間;在沉陷時代大概有更多的滅絕生物,在上升時代大概有更多的變異而且記錄也保存得最不完全;各個單一的地質層不是連續(xù)沉積起來的;各個地質層的持續(xù)時間與物種類型的平均壽命比較起來,大概要短些;任何一個地域、地質層中,遷徙對于新類型的初次出現(xiàn),是有重要作用的;分布廣的物種是變異最頻繁的、最常產(chǎn)生新種的物種;變種最初往往是地方性的。如果把所有這些原因結合起來看,必定會搞得地質記錄極不完整,而且可大致說明為什么我們沒有發(fā)現(xiàn)中間變種以極微細級進的步驟把一切滅絕和現(xiàn)存的生物類型聯(lián)結起來。

凡是不接受關于地質記錄性質的本觀點的人,當然拒絕我的全部理論。他會徒勞地發(fā)問,以前想必把同一個大地質層內若干階段中發(fā)現(xiàn)的密切近似物種或代表物種連接起來的無數(shù)過渡環(huán)節(jié)在哪里呢?他會不相信連續(xù)地質層之間一定要經(jīng)過悠久的間隔期間;他會在單獨考察任何一個大區(qū)域如歐洲的地質層時,忽略了遷徙起著何等重要的作用;他會極力主張整個物種群分明是(往往是假象)突然出現(xiàn)的。他會問,必有不計其數(shù)的生物生活在志留系第一個巖床沉積起來以前很久,但遺骸在哪里呢?我僅能根據(jù)以下的假設來回答這最后的問題,即今日海洋所延伸的地方,海洋已經(jīng)存在了極長久的期間,而上下升降著的大陸在其今日存在之處,自志留紀開始以來就已經(jīng)存在了;而遠在志留紀以前,這個世界呈現(xiàn)了完全不同的景象;由更古地質層形成的古大陸,今日僅以變質狀態(tài)的遺物存在,或者還埋藏在海洋之下。

撇下這些難點,我看古生物學其他的主要重大事實便與通過自然選擇的生物變異傳承學說相符了。我們就可以理解,新物種為什么緩慢而連續(xù)地產(chǎn)生;為什么不同綱的物種不一定一起發(fā)生變化,以同等速度、同等程度發(fā)生變化,然而長遠看一切生物畢竟都發(fā)生了某種程度的變異。老類型的滅絕差不多是新類型產(chǎn)生的必然結果。我們能夠理解為什么一個物種一旦消滅就永不再現(xiàn)。物種群在數(shù)目上的增加是緩慢的,存續(xù)時期也各不相等;變異的過程必然是緩慢的,取決于許多復雜的偶然事件。屬于優(yōu)勢大群的優(yōu)勢物種傾向于留下許多變異后代,由此形成新的亞群和群。新群形成之后,低活力群的物種,由于從共同祖先那里遺傳到劣根性,傾向于一起滅絕,不在地面上留下變異后代。但是物種全群的徹底滅絕往往是極緩慢的過程,因為有少數(shù)后代會在被保護的孤立場所殘存下來。群一旦完全滅絕,就不再出現(xiàn);世代的連鎖環(huán)節(jié)已經(jīng)斷了。

我們能夠理解為什么變異最頻繁的優(yōu)勢類型,長遠看傾向于以親緣的變異后代分布于世界,一般都能夠成功取代生存斗爭中的劣勢群。因此,經(jīng)過長久的間隔期間之后,世界上的生物便呈現(xiàn)曾經(jīng)同時發(fā)生變化的樣子了。

我們能夠理解,為什么古今一切生物類型匯合起來成為一個大系統(tǒng),它們統(tǒng)統(tǒng)世代相連。我們能夠理解,由于性狀分歧的連續(xù)傾向,為什么類型越古,一般與現(xiàn)存類型差異越大;為什么古代的滅絕類型常傾向于把現(xiàn)存物種之間的空隙填補起來,往往把先前被分作兩個不同的群合而為一;但更普通的是只把它們稍微拉近一些。類型越古,在某種程度上越常常呈現(xiàn)在不同的群之間的中間性狀;因為類型越古,與廣為分歧之后的群的共同祖先越接近,從而越相似。滅絕類型很少直接介于現(xiàn)存類型之間,而僅是通過許多不同的類型采取漫長而迂回曲折的路徑。我們能清楚看到,為什么密切連續(xù)的地質層的生物遺骸比遙遠地質層親緣更密切,因為被世代更密切地聯(lián)結在一起之故。我們能清楚看到,為什么中間地質層的生物遺骸具有中間性狀。

世界歷史上各個連續(xù)時代內的生物,在生活競賽中戰(zhàn)勝了祖先,等級上相應地提高了,這可以說明很多古生物學者模糊不清的觀點——體制整體上進步了。滅絕的古代動物在某種程度上都與同綱中近代動物的胚胎相類似,如果今后能證明這一點,事實便會豁然開朗。晚近地質時代中同一結構模式在同一地域內的演替就不再神秘了,根據(jù)傳承原理,可以干凈利落地加以解釋。

這樣,如果地質記錄如我相信的那樣不完全,至少可以斷定這記錄不能被證明更加完全,那么對于自然選擇學說的主要異議就會大事化小小事化了。另一方面,我認為,古生物學的所有主要法則明白地宣告了,物種是由普通的生殖產(chǎn)生出來的:老類型被改進了的新生物類型所淘汰,那是我們周圍仍然起作用的變異法則所致,并且由“自然選擇”保存了下來。

用戶搜索

瘋狂英語 英語語法 新概念英語 走遍美國 四級聽力 英語音標 英語入門 發(fā)音 美語 四級 新東方 七年級 賴世雄 zero是什么意思徐州市松霏花園英語學習交流群

  • 頻道推薦
  • |
  • 全站推薦
  • 推薦下載
  • 網(wǎng)站推薦